《the+critique+of+pure+reason_纯粹理性批判》

下载本书

添加书签

the+critique+of+pure+reason_纯粹理性批判- 第132部分


按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
to fail in clearness; by saying too little on the new subject of
discussion。 I hope to avoid both extremes; by keeping as close as
possible to the transcendental; and excluding all psychological;
that is; empirical; elements。

  *All practical conceptions relate to objects of pleasure and pain;
and consequently… in an indirect manner; at least… to objects of
feeling。 But as feeling is not a faculty of representation; but lies
out of the sphere of our powers of cognition; the elements of our
judgements; in so far as they relate to pleasure or pain; that is; the
elements of our practical judgements; do not belong to
transcendental philosophy; which has to do with pure a priori
cognitions alone。

  I have to remark; in the first place; that at present I treat of the
conception of freedom in the practical sense only; and set aside the
corresponding transcendental conception; which cannot be employed as a
ground of explanation in the phenomenal world; but is itself a problem
for pure reason。 A will is purely animal (arbitrium brutum) when it is
determined by sensuous impulses or instincts only; that is; when it is
determined in a pathological manner。 A will; which can be determined
independently of sensuous impulses; consequently by motives
presented by reason alone; is called a free will (arbitrium
liberum); and everything which is connected with this free will;
either as principle or consequence; is termed practical。 The existence
of practical freedom can be proved from experience alone。 For the
human will is not determined by that alone which immediately affects
the senses; on the contrary; we have the power; by calling up the
notion of what is useful or hurtful in a more distant relation; of
overing the immediate impressions on our sensuous faculty of
desire。 But these considerations of what is desirable in relation to
our whole state; that is; is in the end good and useful; are based
entirely upon reason。 This faculty; accordingly; enounces laws;
which are imperative or objective laws of freedom and which tell us
what ought to take place; thus distinguishing themselves from the laws
of nature; which relate to that which does take place。 The laws of
freedom or of free will are hence termed practical laws。
  Whether reason is not itself; in the actual delivery of these
laws; determined in its turn by other influences; and whether the
action which; in relation to sensuous impulses; we call free; may not;
in relation to higher and more remote operative causes; really form
a part of nature… these are questions which do not here concern us。
They are purely speculative questions; and all we have to do; in the
practical sphere; is to inquire into the rule of conduct which
reason has to present。 Experience demonstrates to us the existence
of practical freedom as one of the causes which exist in nature;
that is; it shows the causal power of reason in the determination of
the will。 The idea of transcendental freedom; on the contrary;
requires that reason… in relation to its causal power of mencing
a series of phenomena… should be independent of all sensuous
determining causes; and thus it seems to be in opposition to the law
of nature and to all possible experience。 It therefore remains a
problem for the human mind。 But this problem does not concern reason
in its practical use; and we have; therefore; in a canon of pure
reason; to do with only two questions; which relate to the practical
interest of pure reason: Is there a God? and; Is there a future
life? The question of transcendental freedom is purely speculative;
and we may therefore set it entirely aside when we e to treat of
practical reason。 Besides; we have already discussed this subject in
the antinomy of pure reason。

   SECTION II。 Of the Ideal of the Summum Bonum as a Determining
           Ground of the Ultimate End of Pure Reason。

  Reason conducted us; in its speculative use; through the field of
experience and; as it can never find plete satisfaction in that
sphere; from thence to speculative ideas… which; however; in the end
brought us back again to experience; and thus fulfilled the purpose of
reason; in a manner which; though useful; was not at all in accordance
with our expectations。 It now remains for us to consider whether
pure reason can be employed in a practical sphere; and whether it will
here conduct us to those ideas which attain the highest ends of pure
reason; as we have just stated them。 We shall thus ascertain
whether; from the point of view of its practical interest; reason
may not be able to supply us with that which; on the speculative side;
it wholly denies us。
  The whole interest of reason; speculative as well as practical; is
centred in the three following questions:

               1。 WHAT CAN I KNOW?
               2。 WHAT OUGHT I TO DO?
               3。 WHAT MAY I HOPE?

  The first question is purely speculative。 We have; as I flatter
myself; exhausted all the replies of which it is susceptible; and have
at last found the reply with which reason must content itself; and
with which it ought to be content; so long as it pays no regard to the
practical。 But from the two great ends to the attainment of which
all these efforts of pure reason were in fact directed; we remain just
as far removed as if we had consulted our ease and declined the task
at the outset。 So far; then; as knowledge is concerned; thus much;
at least; is established; that; in regard to those two problems; it
lies beyond our reach。
  The second question is purely practical。 As such it may indeed
fall within the province of pure reason; but still it is not
transcendental; but moral; and consequently cannot in itself form
the subject of our criticism。
  The third question: If I act as I ought to do; what may I then
hope?… is at once practical and theoretical。 The practical forms a
clue to the answer of the theoretical; and… in its highest form…
speculative question。 For all hoping has happiness for its object
and stands in precisely the same relation to the practical and the law
of morality as knowing to the theoretical cognition of things and
the law of nature。 The former arrives finally at the conclusion that
something is (which determines the ultimate end); because something
ought to take place; the latter; that something is (which operates
as the highest cause); because something does take place。
  Happiness is the satisfaction of all our desires; extensive; in
regard to their multiplicity; intensive; in regard to their degree;
and protensive; in regard to their duration。 The practical law based
on the motive of happiness I term a pragmatical law (or prudential
rule); but that law; assuming such to exist; which has no other motive
than the worthiness of being happy; I term a moral or ethical law。 The
first tells us what we have to do; if we wish to bee possessed of
happiness; the second dictates how we ought to act; in order to
deserve happiness。 The first is based upon empirical principles; for
it is only by experience that I can learn either what inclinations
exist which desire satisfaction; or what are the natural means of
satisfying them。 The second takes no account of our desires or the
means of satisfying them; and regards only the freedom of a rational
being; and the necessary conditions under which alone this freedom can
harmonize with the distribution of happiness according to
principles。 This second law may therefore rest upon mere ideas of pure
reason; and may be cognized a priori。
  I assume that there are pure moral laws which determine; entirely
a priori (without regard to empirical motives; that is; to happiness);
the conduct of a rational being; or in other words; to use which it
makes of its freedom; and that these laws are absolutely imperative
(not merely hypothetically; on the supposition of other empirical
ends); and therefore in all respects necessary。 I am warranted in
assuming this; not only by the arguments of the most enlightened
moralists; but by the moral judgement of every man who will make the
attempt to form a distinct conception of such a law。
  Pure reason; then; contains; not indeed in its speculative; but in
its practical; or; more strictly; its moral use; principles of the
possibility of experience; of such actions; namely; as; in
accordance with ethical precepts; might be met with in the history
of man。 For since reason mands that such actions should take place;
it must be possible for them to take place; and hence a particular
kind of systematic unity… the moral… must be possible。 We have
found; it is true; that the systematic unity of nature could not be
established according to speculative principles of reason; because;
while reason possesses a causal power in relation to freedom; it has
none in relation to the whole sphere of nature; and; while moral
principles of reason can produce free actions; they cannot produce
natural laws。 It is; then; in its practical; but especially in its
moral use; that the principles of pure reason possess objective
reality。
  I call the world a moral world; in so far as it may be in accordance
with all the ethical laws… which; by virtue of the freedom of
reasonable beings
小提示:按 回车 [Enter] 键 返回书目,按 ← 键 返回上一页, 按 → 键 进入下一页。 赞一下 添加书签加入书架